Arendt On Life and Love of the World

Arendt is famously adamant that politics cannot and should not devote itself to issues focused on the maintenance of life.  Attending to such issues can only lead to disaster, as exemplified by the French Revolution being hijacked by the enrages.  Lurking underneath her analysis of the French Revolution, one suspects, is a fierce anti-communism.  The problem with Marxism (she implies without ever fully stating) is that it turns politics over to “questions of life,” to precisely “economic” issues, and thus a) loses what is distinctive and valuable about the political and b) leads to the massive infliction of death, a terror that makes the sins of Robespierre pale in comparison.

Why doesn’t Arendt condemn Marxism forthrightly?  Because she is appalled by the know-nothing anti-communism of McCarthy and his ilk in the 1950s America and does not want to be welcomed into their camp as a fellow traveler.  But, as starkly as Hayek, Arendt insists that the economy is private and must remain private.  The dire consequences of mixing economic and politics are actually not that far different in Arendt’s analysis as in Hayek’s.  He predicts “serfdom,” she sees an inability to access the “freedom” that action enables (where action—as distinct from labor and work– is only possible in the political realm.)  Only action, in Arendt’s theory, is free.  Labor and work unfold under the sign of “necessity.”  And it is fair to say that in both Hayek and Arendt, “justice” (or, at least, “social justice” which concerns itself with a fair distribution of material goods along with equal protection under the law and equal access to political participation) gets short shrift.  Very explicitly in Hayek, who fulminates against the “mirage” of social justice and sees “envy” as the only motivation driving any effort to achieve social justice.  But almost as explicitly in Arendt, who seems to think the attempt to achieve such justice by the French revolutionaries as a destructive quest to the impossible.  To attach politics to the promise of ending poverty is to raise hopes for a goal that cannot be reached—and the resultant disappointment generates a fury that tears society apart.  In On Revolution, Arendt appears as fatalistic as Hayek about the possibility of achieving anything remotely like economic equality.  Rather, political equality can be achieved, but only by building an impenetrable border between inevitable economic inequality and the equality that is to reign in the “space of appearances.”  One type of status (economic status) is to have no impact, no bearing on a different kind of status, the political status enjoyed by the citizen.

The problem in the real world, of course, is that status and power don’t work that way.  Power clings to status, but is mobile (extremely so) from one form of status to another.  You can’t build a wall to keep economic power from generating political power.  Rousseau was right to say that economic inequality was fatal to democracy.  Plutocracy is the almost inevitable result of tolerating large economic inequalities.

Arendt does have an escape clause in her reflections on these issues—one that she, oddly enough, borrows from Marx.  Oddly because she is generally anti-Marxist (because he substitutes economics for politics) and because the notion she does adopt is one of the most implausible Marxist tenets.  Economic matters, Arendt claims in several places, are merely matters of “administration,” not of politics.  Marx, of course, argued that the state would wither away in a classless society, leaving only the question of the “administration of things” (a wonderfully vague phrase).  The idea seems to be that such administrative matters are conflict-free, simple questions of means.  Politics is the realm of conflict, of argument, of disagreement—which Marx abhors and wants to abolish and which Arendt celebrates and wants to enhance.  But such Arendtian conflict is never to be over material things—or, at least, over the distribution of material things.  Or something like that.  I am not the first to complain that it is not clear what Arendtian politics is “about.”  She wants a free space of appearances where opinions are enunciated—and sees that speaking in public in agonistic deliberation with one’s equals as uniquely identity forming.  But she rarely, if ever, considers the end point of those deliberations.  In fact, she insists that the “action” which is epitomized by that public speaking is “unproductive.”

Now, in one sense, I think it fair to say that Arendt’s idea is something like this.  We can all have an “opinion” about whether or not a bridge should be built over the river.  We can offer reasons in a public debate about this decision, but there is no “truth” of the matter.  Politics, then, would encompass the deliberation.  But once the decision to build the bridge is made, its actual construction is a matter of “administration.”  You call in the engineers and they get it done.  It is not a matter of opinion, something we can argue about, to construct a bridge that can actually carry traffic without collapsing.  “Truth,” which she calls “pre-political” (or maybe should be considered “apolitical”) takes over when it comes to the engineering decisions.

An obvious problem, of course, is that many “administrative” matters are much less cut and dried than building a bridge.  (And even with the bridge, there will be disagreements about its look, and constraints connected to budget, amounts of traffic, availability of materials etc., some of which will entail debate beyond the expertise of the engineers.)  Thus, for example, we can agree, after deliberation, that we want to decrease infant mortality rates. But there are no cut and dried methods that advance that goal, while there are also trade-offs involved (i.e. non-desirable side effects) with any method we do choose.  There will be disagreements, then, about effectiveness and about the extent to which we should tolerate negative side-effects.  Just as it proves difficult to segregate economic power/status from political power/status, it proves difficult to segregate “administrative decisions” from “political decisions” (about which we expect and even welcome disagreement and spirited debate).

Arendt’s escape clause does not only entail adopting the idea of non-political administration.  She also, again in a quasi-Marxist way, seems to believe we are living in, or are on the verge of living in, a post-scarcity society.  Our productive capacities have now reached the point where poverty will be abolished if we just administer things correctly.  For the first time in history, every person (not just the citizen, not just the make head of household, not just the non-slave) will have the leisure to step into the public arena as an equal among equals.  The terrible reign of labor, the drudgery of producing the necessities of life, will come to an end.

To Arendt, unlike Marx, the terrible danger is not that this potential to end poverty will be derailed by an unequal distribution of the goods modern technology produces.  She pays no heed to the economic imperatives—namely the drives to profit and accumulation—that will generate “poverty amidst plenty.”  Rather, she is worried (in classic 1950s style) about the psychological pathologies of “consumer culture.”  What she, with a mandarin distaste and disdain that links her to her supposed nemesis Adorno, rails against are bourgeois subjects so enthralled by consumer goods, by the baubles connected to an enhanced life (but still “life”), that they will willingly work harder and harder to buy more “labor-saving devices,” instead of using their potential liberation from labor to embrace (non-productive) political action and freedom.  The moderns have lost their taste for, even any understanding of, “freedom,” and are addicted to “necessities”—ever more elaborate meals, houses, clothes etc.

On another hand, action is not entirely non-productive.  What it produces is the conditions of its own possibility.  (Arendt was nothing if not a Kantian; she is always attuned to enabling conditions.)  By appearing together in a public square to speak and act is to constitute that public square.  It does not exist except when we inhabit it together doing our thing.  When we go back home, it dissolves.  (Arendt is mostly antipathetic to institutions, associating them with a reification akin to rigor mortis.  Certainly, she never really considers the nature of institutions—and the way that they can provide some kind of stability, even permanence, that what is transitory.  She obviously greatly prefers the spontaneity of what is produced through actual interactions over the formal structures that people devise to give those spontaneous productions a chance to survive beyond the moment of their creation.)  Arendt, in her most grandiloquent moments, calls that public sphere, that space of appearances, “the world.”

Quite basically, Arendt says we will have disaster if we do not have people who “love the world.”  Practically, that means people who prefer the political action that produces the space of appearances over the pleasures of consumption.  Non-productive action produces nothing except the political realm that makes that action possible.  The circularity here can be head-ache inducing.  Still, Arendt insists that there is something to be called “public happiness” and that happiness is the “lost treasure of revolutions.”  It is a heady pleasure discovered in the “acting in concert” that is a political movement, and is a pleasure disconnected from whether the movement succeeds in achieving its stated goals or not.  For Occupy, the focus on that pleasure, on that creation together of a space to occupy, made even enunciating goals irrelevant—and even threatening.  The point was this space the occupiers had created, not some leverage toward change in some other space.  Creating our own world was the point, not influencing some other world.

What Arendt fears, then, is that attachment to “life” means attachment to consuming, to the pleasures associated with satisfying bodily necessities.  She wants to advocate for a different set, a different order, of desires, ones connected to sociality, to what can only come into being intersubjectively, collectively.

Thus Arendt, like Ruskin and Mill, is worried about an attachment to life that is overly bodily, or bestial.  (I am thinking of Mill’s famous passage about a swinish life as not worthy of human beings.)  We have a “higher” destiny for Arendt—and she is contemptuous of those for whom working toward acquiring a second car and a vacation home provides more than enough meaning in their lives.  We can go even further, I think, and say that Arendt buys into the basic premise of Hegel’s master/slave dialectic.  To be overly attached to life, to have nothing that you value enough above life to actually forfeit life to preserve that more valuable thing, is to be a slave.  Life can’t be the highest value is you want to be human, to be more than a beast.  There must be something you identify as unlivable, some set of conditions that you would not tolerate, and that you would die rather than endure.  (In her later work, Arendt will associate this idea with Socrates, and insist that “when the chips are down,” the “moral” human would have chosen death over submission to the evil—no matter if understood as radical or banal—of the Nazis.)  To return to the vocabulary of The Human Condition and On Revolution, to take “life” as the highest value is to chain oneself to “necessity.”  Life compels; it confines us to “labor,” to the production of those necessities that sustain it.  Freedom, the opposite of necessity, is only available to the person who refuses to cede life such power, who refuses to says that its claims trump all others.  “The world” is one way Arendt designates that “other” to life, that something else to which we can pledge allegiance, which we can learn (?) to “love.”

The story doesn’t end there.  There are issues of “organized remembrance” and “meaning” still to be addressed.  So that’s where I am headed next.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s